A) About missing things
1. When
something is lost, we can still feel its presence around us. It is a memory in
our mind which we will keep alive (even if it becomes fainter with time) for as
long as we live. But it is not only the things which used to be but now are
gone, but also the things which have never existed, yet they seem to be around
us, sometimes as essential as real things, influencing our lives and defining
reality. Leaving aside God (which is one of such ghostly things and a matter of
religion), we can mention the numbers and the forces, which are the basis of
the positive sciences, the soul or the mind (and its physical counterpart the
brain), which are the subject of psychology and neurology, and finally the
human being, its origin and purpose, as the subject of philosophy.
B)
The notion of infinitesimals
2. According
to a definition, infinitesimals are defined as things so small that there is no
way to measure them. Infinitesimals are a basic ingredient in the procedures of
infinitesimal calculus as developed by Leibniz. In common speech,
‘infinitesimal’ means ‘extremely small,’ but not zero. To give it a meaning, it
usually must be compared to another infinitesimal object in the same context
(as in a derivative). The insight with exploiting infinitesimals was that
entities could still retain certain specific properties, such as angle or slope,
even though these entities were quantitatively small. [1]
C)
Berkeley’s argument
3. Although
infinitesimals and their discipline (infinitesimal calculus) introduced the
notion of instantaneous change (or simply of change) in modern science, and
offered a method to calculate that change, their origin and validity as ‘real
objects’ remains obscure and ambiguous. For example, are all infinitesimals
equal in size? When we keep on dividing a quantity, will we be left with
something measurable in the end? Is ‘zero’ a miniscule ‘something’ or an
absolute ‘nothing?’ If we divide infinity into an infinite number of smaller
parts, are those parts infinitesimals or infinites themselves? What is the fundamental difference between something
infinitely ‘small’ and something infinitely ‘large?’ Is there any difference
after all? Or is it the quality of things (and of the mind thinking about the
things) what finally decides their true size?
4. Here
is a relative argument stated by Berkeley, with respect to infinitesimals:
“It must, indeed, be acknowledged, that [Newton] used fluxions,
like the scaffold of a building, as things to be laid aside or got rid of, as
soon as finite lines were found proportional to them. But then these finite exponents
are found by the help of fluxions. Whatever therefore is got by such exponents
and proportions is to be ascribed to fluxions: which must therefore be
previously understood. And what are these fluxions? The velocities of
evanescent increments? And what are these same evanescent increments? They are
neither finite quantities nor quantities infinitely small, nor yet nothing. May
we not call them the ghosts of departed quantities?” [2]
D)
The paradox of the derivative
5. The
notion of a ‘fluxion’ has been substituted by that of a derivative. Instantaneous
velocity is the derivative of the position with respect to time- at the limit
where the time interval is infinitesimally small. Can however division by zero
be defined? If not then the whole discipline of infinitesimal calculus is
invalid, since it uses ratios of infinitesimal quantities. Thus Berkeley’s
objection.
6. Although
one may ignore the division by zero which appears in the calculation of a
derivative, so that one may take in the end the correct result (e.g. a
measurement of instantaneous velocity), the mathematical problem is still
there: if zero is ‘nothing’ then how can one divide something by nothing? Even
if we can finally ignore the problem, there is a logical fallacy in the roots
of the mathematical method. Is this because human logic is imperfect? Is it
perhaps because ‘zero’ is not ‘nothing,’ but a real quantity (although very
small)? Or is it just because motion (and change in general) is impossible?
E)
Zeno’s paradox of motion
7. This
is a set of philosophical problems which have been devised to support the doctrine
that contrary to the evidence of one’s senses, the belief in plurality and
change is mistaken, and in particular that motion is nothing but an illusion.
8. Three
of those paradoxes are the following:
a)
Achilles and the tortoise: In a race, the
quickest runner can never overtake the slowest, since the pursuer must first
reach the point whence the pursued started, so that the slower must always hold
a lead.
b)
Dichotomy paradox: That which is in locomotion
must arrive at the half-way stage before it arrives at the goal.
c)
Arrow paradox: If everything when it occupies an
equal space is at rest, and if that which is in locomotion is always occupying
such a space at any moment, the flying arrow is therefore motionless. [3]
F)
The method of exhaustion
9. Perhaps
the most ingenious method which has ever been discovered to treat the problem
of infinity in logic and mathematics is Archimedes’ method of exhaustion. The
method of exhaustion is a method of finding the area of a shape by inscribing inside
it a sequence of polygons whose areas converge to the area of the containing
shape. As the difference in area between the polygons and the containing shape
becomes arbitrarily small, the area of the shape is systematically ‘exhausted’
(its correct value is being approached). [4]
10. An
application of this method is finding the sum of an infinite series. For
example if we add half a distance to half of what’s left, and so on, we take
the whole distance as result (1/2+1/4+1/8+…=1). Thus one might argue that this
way we can solve Zeno’s dichotomy paradox. However the previous series which
converges to unity is in fact infinite. Thus we need an infinite number of
subdivisions to have unity as result.
G)
Making a quantum step
11. A
way out of this logical problem of infinite regress- an infinitesimal quantity
which gets smaller and smaller, without ever vanishing (or ‘departing,’ as
Berkeley would say), is the notion of the quantum in quantum mechanics.
According to this discipline all action (thus motion) is quantized. A quantum
(such as a photon) is a very small quantity, but it is not zero. Even empty
space is not completely empty, but consists of quanta of minimal energy (vacuum
energy). Therefore, according to quantum mechanics, we can divide space into
very small quanta which are not zero, so that adding them up we can get as
result a macroscopic distance. Again however the problem is that the quantum is
not a well- defined quantity. A quantum can be arbitrarily small, so that,
after a limit, as quanta get smaller and smaller, quantum mechanics breaks
down. Thus the problem of infinity resurfaces.
H)
Motion is reconstructed by the mind
12. In
relation to the arrow paradox, when we watch an arrow flying what we truly
perceive is not the arrow moving but the arrow changing its position at regular
and fixed intervals. What we really measure is the time, while the arrow helps
us to perceive the passage of time. Therefore what is really passing by is not
the ‘arrow’ but the ‘time.’
13. Thus
we might say that time is the invisible
thing which is materialized and perceived in the form of an arrow. This is
the same as measuring our pulse: What do we really measure? Is it the blood
pressure? Is it the heart rate? Is it the ticking of the clock? It is as if we
were counting the vibrations of our soul materializing into different
perceivable objects. Thus we might say that motion is an aspect which -either
it exists in the outer world or not- is reconstructed by the mind.
14. A
critical aspect of infinity is that in fact it can be either very big or very
small. At the subatomic level even a grain of sand may look like the universe,
but at the macroscopic level the whole universe may be just an infinitesimal
part of the multiverse. Therefore it depends on the angle and the scale we use to
approach the problem of infinity. In fact in our mind either a universe or a
grain of sand ‘equally fit.’ Although we assume that the universe must be much
bigger than a grain of sand, when we think about it the difference between
these two objects is not their size but their meaning. Furthermore, with
respect to time or distance to be traveled, the time it takes for us to travel
at the other end of the universe with our imagination is no longer or shorter
than the time it takes us to blink our eyes.
15. Is it finally the qualities of our own mind what define the quantities of the objects which we perceive as real and moving? Is there something lying in imagination (beyond reason) what makes reason credible?
15. Is it finally the qualities of our own mind what define the quantities of the objects which we perceive as real and moving? Is there something lying in imagination (beyond reason) what makes reason credible?
I)
What if the ghosts of the departed quantities are
the manifestations of the incredible things to come?
[1] [https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Infinitesimal]
[2] [https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/The_Analyst]
[3] [https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Zeno%27s_paradoxes]
[4] [https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Method_of_exhaustion]
8/27/2018
Picture: [https://sites.psu.edu/math140/sample-page/the-derivatives/definition-of-derivative/]
No comments:
Post a Comment